Lexical Realisation Unit

From UNL Wiki
(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
(LRUs are standardized lexical realisations for concepts)
m (Lexical Realisation Unit (LRU))
 
(72 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
In the UNLarium framework, a '''lexical realisation unit''' (or simply '''LRU''') is any discrete, recurring and standardized unit of meaning of a given natural language. It can be a morpheme (a root, an affix), a simple word or a multi-word expression (compounds, collocations, idioms). The set of LRUs constitutes the '''vocabulary''' or the '''lexicon''' of a language.
+
In the UNLarium framework, a '''Lexical Realisation Unit''' (or simply '''LRU''') is the natural language counterpart to a [[UW]]. It can be a subword (a root, an affix), a simple word or a multiword expression (compounds, collocations, idioms).  
  
== LRUs are standardized lexical realisations for concepts ==  
+
== Lexical realisation (LR) ==  
The UNLarium is first and foremost a generation-driven framework, which has been developed mainly to provide resources for generating natural language texts out of UNL graphs. In that sense, UNLarium entries should correspond to the most likely '''realisations''', in a given language, of a given concept. The expression “realisation" stands here for a mixture of wording and phrasing, i.e., the manner in which a concept is articulated in a given language. For instance, the concept “the natural satellite of the Earth” is realised, in English, by the word “Moon”; in French, by “lune”; in German, by “Mond”; in Russian, by “луна”; in Spanish, by “luna”; in Chinese, by 月; and so on. Your first task in the UNLarium is exactly to find out linguistic realisations for concepts, which will be always presented by their corresponding definition in English.  
+
The UNLarium is first and foremost a generation-driven framework, which has been developed mainly to provide resources for generating natural language texts out of UNL graphs. In that sense, UNLarium entries should correspond to the most likely '''realisations''', in a given language, of a given concept (i.e., a '''UW'''). The expression “realisation" stands here for a mixture of wording and phrasing, i.e., the manner in which the concept is articulated in a given language. For instance, the UW 109358358 (= “the natural satellite of the Earth”) is realised, in English, by the word “moon”; in French, by “lune”; in German, by “Mond”; in Russian, by “луна”; in Spanish, by “luna”; in Chinese, by 月; and so on. Your first task in the UNLarium is exactly to find out linguistic realisations for UWs, which will be always presented by their corresponding definition in English.  
  
LRUs, however, are not simply linguistic realisations; they are '''lexical''' realisations. This means that LRUs should correspond to the units of the vocabulary of a language, i.e., to a lexical item. Let’s come back to our previous example. Apart from “Moon”, the concept “the natural satellite of the Earth” can be realised, in English, by the very expression “the natural satellite of the Earth”, which is indeed very frequent (2.130.000 occurrences in Google). This expression, however, is a “definition” rather than a “lexical realisation” for the concept, and should not correspond to a LRU.
+
LRs, however, are not simply linguistic realisations; they are '''lexical''' realisations. This means that LRs should correspond to the units of the vocabulary of a language, i.e., to a "lexical item". Let’s come back to our previous example. Apart from “moon”, the UW 109358358 can be realised, in English, by the expression “the natural satellite of the Earth”, which is indeed very frequent (2.130.000 occurrences in Google). This expression, however, is a “definition” rather than a “lexical realisation” for the UW, and should therefore not correspond to a LR.
  
The differences between definitions and lexical items, or between “defining” and “naming” a concept, are fairly subjective, and are normally ascribed to the compositionality (or analyticity) of the candidate term: if the meaning of the compound can be reduced to the combination of the meaning of its components, it is said to be simply a definition; otherwise, i.e., if there is a sort of semantic surplus, a supplementary (or even complementary) sense added to the simple combination, the term is considered a lexical item. Consider, for instance, the case of “sweet and sour”. In this case, we have clearly a lexical item and therefore a LRU, because the phrase encompasses the sense of “sauce” that cannot be derived from the combination of the meanings of “sweet”, “and”, “sour”, even if, in the past, the expression was merely a conjunction of two simple adjectives. As a matter of fact, the process of converting definitions into lexical items is very common and one of the most frequent strategies employed to increase and improve the vocabulary of a language.
+
The differences between definitions and lexical items, or between “defining” and “naming” a concept, are fairly subjective, and are normally ascribed to the compositionality (or analyticity) of the candidate term: if the meaning of the compound can be reduced to the combination of the meaning of its components, it is said to be simply a definition; otherwise, i.e., if there is a sort of semantic surplus, a supplementary (or even complementary) sense added to the simple combination, the term is considered a lexical item. The above-mentioned expression "the natural satellite of the Earth", for instance, does not bring any new semantic content to the ones conveyed by its components. This is not the case of "geostationary communications satellite", which subsumes the idea of "orbit" which is not explicitly present in the compound. Accordingly, "geostationary communications satellite" (208.000 occurrences in Google) should be treated as a LR, whereas "the natural satellite of the Earth", in spite of its higher frequency, should not.
  
Finally, LRUs have also to be '''standardized''' lexical realisations for concepts. This means that LRUs must have been already consolidated, which can be verified in dictionaries and glossaries, or by the rate of recurrence in the Web. If the structure is reasonably constant and convincingly recurring, it is a LRU; otherwise, it is not.  
+
== Lexical Realisation Unit (LRU) ==
But be careful: the frequency condition applies after the lexical (combinatorial) one. Notice that “the natural satellite of the Earth” is not a LRU, in spite of its 2.130.000 occurrences, whereas “sweet and sour”, with 1.710.000 occurrences, is a LRU.
+
In synthetic (inflected) languages, such as the Indo-European ones, a single UW may be realised by different lexical realisations in order to express different grammatical categories, such as number, gender, tense and case. The UW 200358431 (= “pass from physical life and lose all bodily attributes and functions necessary to sustain life”), for instance, is realised, in English, by the forms "to die", "die", "dies", "dying", "died", "dead", "will die", etc. These LRs are said to be different forms of the same '''Lexical Realisation Unit''' (or LRU).
  
== LRUs are not words ==
+
Lexical Realisation Units are therefore abstract underlying units shared by different lexical realisations, but they should not be mistaken for lexemes. Indeed, it is not very simple to associate the idea of LRU to that of a lexeme, as LRUs may correspond to different morphological structures:
A common misunderstanding in natural language description is that, due to our writing conventions, especially in the Western tradition, we tend to reduce the lexicon of a language to a list of “words”, which are normally understood as the smallest free forms, or the strings of alphabetic characters isolated by blank spaces. Unfortunately, it is not that simple. The vocabulary of a language is made not only of words, but of parts of words (roots, stems, affixes, particles) and of multi-word expressions (compounds, collocations, idioms). In English, one of the most frequent lexical realisations for the concept “contrary of” is the prefix “un-“, which is a bound morpheme (i.e., a semantic unit that does not have an independent existence); in the same way, the concept “allow or plan for a certain possibility” is frequently realised by the phrasal verb “to take (sth) into account”, which is a complex structure that does not figure as a separate entry in most English dictionaries (it is normally listed inside the verb “to take”). So, it is important to understand that “lexical realisation unit”, here, means not only “words”, in the common sense, but any part of the vocabulary of a language.
+
*roots (such as "anthropo", which is one of the possible LRUs for the UW 102472293 = “any living or extinct member of the family Hominidae characterized by superior intelligence, articulate speech, and erect carriage");
 +
*stems (such as "unhappy", which is one of the possible LRUs for the UW 301149494 = "experiencing or marked by or causing sadness or sorrow or discontent"); and
 +
*word forms (such as "glasses", which is one of the possible LRUs for the UW 104272054 = "optical instrument consisting of a pair of lenses for correcting defective vision").
  
== LRUs are not roots ==
+
Additionally, LRUs may also correspond to complex structures comprising several different (and even discontinuous) lexemes, as in "geostationary communications satellite" or "throw <someone> to the lions".
In synthetic (inflected) languages, such as the Indo-European ones, a single LRU may be articulated to several different forms in order to express different grammatical categories, such as number, gender, tense and case. The definition “pass from physical life and lose all bodily attributes and functions necessary to sustain life”, for instance, is present, in English, in the forms "to die" (infinitive), "die" (present tense except 3rd person singular), "dies" (3rd person singular of the present tense), "dying" (gerund), "died" (past tense), "dead" (past participle), "will die" (future), etc. Only the forms "die", "dy-" and "d-", however, actually realise the intended definition, which does not comprise any particular value for tense or mood. Particles (such as "to"), affixes (such as the inflectional suffixes "-s", "-ing", "-ed") and co-verbs (such as the auxiliary "will") convey different notions and should be isolated in order to obtain the real LRU.  Nevertheless, this does not mean that LRUs are roots. As "lexical realisations" of definitions, LRUs may correspond either to single-rooted forms (such as “die”) or to multiple-root compounds (such as “kick the bucket” or “give up the ghost”).  
+
  
== LRUs are variable ==
+
== Lexical Realisation Set (LRS) ==  
Apart form inflections, LRUs may vary in many different senses: spelling (such as in the allomorphs “die” and “dy” above), discontinuity (as in “take […] into account”) and order (as in German separable verbs such as “angekommen” and “kommen” […] “an”). These variants are said to be simply instances of the same LRU, which should be treated as a class rather than a single element, even in case of radical changes (such as the forms of the irregular verb "to be" in English: “be”, “am”, “are”, “was”, etc). The possible variations of a given LRU will be informed through inflectional and subcategorization rules in a different field.
+
  
== How to express a LRU ==
+
As languages have different lexicalisation processes, a single definition may correspond to several different LRUs, which are said to be '''synonyms'''. The UW 200358431 (“pass from physical life and lose all bodily attributes and functions necessary to sustain life”), for instance, may be realised in English by several different LRs: “die”, “croak”, “decease”, “drop dead”, “buy the farm”, “cash in one's chips”, “give-up the ghost”, “kick the bucket”, “pass away”, “perish”, “snuff it”, “pop off”, “expire”, “conk”, “exit”, “choke”, “go”, “pass”, etc. In such cases, all LRUs should be informed in the UNLarium inside a single '''Lexical Realisation Set''' (LRS).  
To assure readability and to allow the reference to all instances of the same LRU, the LRU is represented, in the UNLarium, through a '''lemma''', i.e., a canonical (citation) form, which is the entry form normally given in ordinary dictionaries and glossaries. The lemma is the form of the singular, for nouns; of the masculine singular, for adjectives; and the infinitive, for verbs. The lemma should follow the spelling and the capitalization rules of the target language. In English, only proper names should bring the initial upper case, whereas in German all nouns should be written this way.
+
  
== Lexicalisation divergences ==
+
There are cases, however, in which the definition cannot be lexically realised in the target language. This happens in two situations:
As languages have different lexicalisation processes, a single definition may correspond to several different LRUs, which are said to be '''synonyms'''. The definition “pass from physical life and lose all bodily attributes and functions necessary to sustain life”, for instance, may be realised in English by several different LRUs: “die”, “croak”, “decease”, “drop dead”, “buy the farm”, “cash in one's chips”, “give-up the ghost”, “kick the bucket”, “pass away”, “perish”, “snuff it”, “pop off”, “expire”, “conk”, “exit”, “choke”, “go”, “pass”, etc. In such cases, all realisations should be informed in the UNLarium.
+
*When the concept is '''underspecified''', i.e., too broad (or vague) to be realised. The concept of “red entity”, for instance, may be coextensive with several different English LRUs (“blood”, “cherry”, “ruby”, “ketchup”, “Spiderman”, etc), but these are rather '''subordinate terms''' (or '''hyponyms'''), in the sense they only include and partly match the intended sense. As the expression “red entity” itself is too compositional and too occasional to be considered already lexicalized (Google brings only 8,040 occurrences for this bigram), there will no LRU in this case.  
 
+
There are cases, however, in which the definition cannot be lexically realised [by a single lexical unit] in the target language. This happens in two situations:
+
*When the concept is '''underspecified''', i.e., too broad (or vague) to be realised. The concept of “red entity”, for instance, may be coextensive with several different English LRUs (“blood”, “cherry”, “ruby”, “ketchup”, “Spiderman”, etc), but these are rather '''subordinate terms''' (or '''hyponyms'''), in the sense they only include and partly match the intended sense. And the expression “red entity” itself is too compositional and too occasional to be considered already lexicalized (Google brings only 8,040 occurrences for this bigram).  
+
 
*When the concept is '''overspecified''', i.e., too narrow (or specific) to be realised. Consider, for instance, the definition “a person who is ready to forgive any transgression a first time and then to tolerate it for a second time, but never for a third time”. This definition does not lead to any LRU in English, French or Russian, even though it corresponds to a single word (“ilunga”) in Tshiluba, a language spoken in the Republic of Congo. We may obviously express the concept in any language, but we have to do it through a periphrasis (as we have done for English) or through a '''superordinate term''' (or '''hypernym'''), such as “forgiver”, “excuser”, “pardoner”, which are again fairly accurate.  
 
*When the concept is '''overspecified''', i.e., too narrow (or specific) to be realised. Consider, for instance, the definition “a person who is ready to forgive any transgression a first time and then to tolerate it for a second time, but never for a third time”. This definition does not lead to any LRU in English, French or Russian, even though it corresponds to a single word (“ilunga”) in Tshiluba, a language spoken in the Republic of Congo. We may obviously express the concept in any language, but we have to do it through a periphrasis (as we have done for English) or through a '''superordinate term''' (or '''hypernym'''), such as “forgiver”, “excuser”, “pardoner”, which are again fairly accurate.  
  
In both cases, there will be no realisation to be informed, and it is important to indicate, in the UNLarium, that the concept has not been lexicalized yet, which means that it can be expressed in the target language only by means of definitions (periphrases) and other semantically related (and inaccurate) lexical units (such as hyponyms or hypernyms).
+
In both cases, there will be no realisation to be informed, and it is important to indicate, in the UNLarium, that the concept has not been lexicalized yet, which means that it can be expressed in the target language only by means of definitions (periphrases) and other semantically related (and inaccurate) LRUs (such as hyponyms or hypernyms). This is done by informing that the Lexical Realisation Set is empty.
  
 
== Examples ==
 
== Examples ==
Line 37: Line 33:
 
!Concept
 
!Concept
 
!Lexical Realisations
 
!Lexical Realisations
!Lexical Realisation Units (LRUs)
+
!Lexical Realisation Unit (LRU)
 
|-
 
|-
 
|width="30%"|large gregarious predatory feline of Africa and India having a tawny coat with a shaggy mane in the male
 
|width="30%"|large gregarious predatory feline of Africa and India having a tawny coat with a shaggy mane in the male
|width="30%"|lion, lions
+
|width="30%"|lion, lions, king of beasts, kings of beasts, Panthera leo
|width="30%"|lion
+
|width="30%"|lion, king of beasts, Panthera leo
 
|-
 
|-
 
|a female lion
 
|a female lion
 
|lioness, lionesses
 
|lioness, lionesses
 
|lioness
 
|lioness
 +
|-
 +
|a large and densely populated urban area
 +
|city, cities, metropolis, urban center, urban centers
 +
|city, metropolis, urban center
 +
|-
 +
|the part of the leg of a human being below the ankle joint
 +
|foot, feet, human foot, human feet, pes
 +
|foot, human foot, pes
 
|-
 
|-
 
|the largest city in New York State and in the United States
 
|the largest city in New York State and in the United States
Line 64: Line 68:
 
|-
 
|-
 
|a person whose occupation is teaching
 
|a person whose occupation is teaching
|professor (male singular), professores (male plural), professora (female singular), professoras (female plural) (Spanish)
+
|profesor (male singular), profesores (male plural), profesora (female singular), profesoras (female plural) (Spanish)
|professor
+
|profesor
 
|-
 
|-
 
|solid-hoofed herbivorous quadruped domesticated since prehistoric times
 
|solid-hoofed herbivorous quadruped domesticated since prehistoric times
Line 100: Line 104:
 
|-
 
|-
 
|in a willing manner
 
|in a willing manner
|gladly
+
|gladly, lief, fain
|gladly
+
|gladly, lief, fain
 
|}
 
|}

Latest revision as of 04:49, 7 July 2018

In the UNLarium framework, a Lexical Realisation Unit (or simply LRU) is the natural language counterpart to a UW. It can be a subword (a root, an affix), a simple word or a multiword expression (compounds, collocations, idioms).

Contents

Lexical realisation (LR)

The UNLarium is first and foremost a generation-driven framework, which has been developed mainly to provide resources for generating natural language texts out of UNL graphs. In that sense, UNLarium entries should correspond to the most likely realisations, in a given language, of a given concept (i.e., a UW). The expression “realisation" stands here for a mixture of wording and phrasing, i.e., the manner in which the concept is articulated in a given language. For instance, the UW 109358358 (= “the natural satellite of the Earth”) is realised, in English, by the word “moon”; in French, by “lune”; in German, by “Mond”; in Russian, by “луна”; in Spanish, by “luna”; in Chinese, by 月; and so on. Your first task in the UNLarium is exactly to find out linguistic realisations for UWs, which will be always presented by their corresponding definition in English.

LRs, however, are not simply linguistic realisations; they are lexical realisations. This means that LRs should correspond to the units of the vocabulary of a language, i.e., to a "lexical item". Let’s come back to our previous example. Apart from “moon”, the UW 109358358 can be realised, in English, by the expression “the natural satellite of the Earth”, which is indeed very frequent (2.130.000 occurrences in Google). This expression, however, is a “definition” rather than a “lexical realisation” for the UW, and should therefore not correspond to a LR.

The differences between definitions and lexical items, or between “defining” and “naming” a concept, are fairly subjective, and are normally ascribed to the compositionality (or analyticity) of the candidate term: if the meaning of the compound can be reduced to the combination of the meaning of its components, it is said to be simply a definition; otherwise, i.e., if there is a sort of semantic surplus, a supplementary (or even complementary) sense added to the simple combination, the term is considered a lexical item. The above-mentioned expression "the natural satellite of the Earth", for instance, does not bring any new semantic content to the ones conveyed by its components. This is not the case of "geostationary communications satellite", which subsumes the idea of "orbit" which is not explicitly present in the compound. Accordingly, "geostationary communications satellite" (208.000 occurrences in Google) should be treated as a LR, whereas "the natural satellite of the Earth", in spite of its higher frequency, should not.

Lexical Realisation Unit (LRU)

In synthetic (inflected) languages, such as the Indo-European ones, a single UW may be realised by different lexical realisations in order to express different grammatical categories, such as number, gender, tense and case. The UW 200358431 (= “pass from physical life and lose all bodily attributes and functions necessary to sustain life”), for instance, is realised, in English, by the forms "to die", "die", "dies", "dying", "died", "dead", "will die", etc. These LRs are said to be different forms of the same Lexical Realisation Unit (or LRU).

Lexical Realisation Units are therefore abstract underlying units shared by different lexical realisations, but they should not be mistaken for lexemes. Indeed, it is not very simple to associate the idea of LRU to that of a lexeme, as LRUs may correspond to different morphological structures:

  • roots (such as "anthropo", which is one of the possible LRUs for the UW 102472293 = “any living or extinct member of the family Hominidae characterized by superior intelligence, articulate speech, and erect carriage");
  • stems (such as "unhappy", which is one of the possible LRUs for the UW 301149494 = "experiencing or marked by or causing sadness or sorrow or discontent"); and
  • word forms (such as "glasses", which is one of the possible LRUs for the UW 104272054 = "optical instrument consisting of a pair of lenses for correcting defective vision").

Additionally, LRUs may also correspond to complex structures comprising several different (and even discontinuous) lexemes, as in "geostationary communications satellite" or "throw <someone> to the lions".

Lexical Realisation Set (LRS)

As languages have different lexicalisation processes, a single definition may correspond to several different LRUs, which are said to be synonyms. The UW 200358431 (“pass from physical life and lose all bodily attributes and functions necessary to sustain life”), for instance, may be realised in English by several different LRs: “die”, “croak”, “decease”, “drop dead”, “buy the farm”, “cash in one's chips”, “give-up the ghost”, “kick the bucket”, “pass away”, “perish”, “snuff it”, “pop off”, “expire”, “conk”, “exit”, “choke”, “go”, “pass”, etc. In such cases, all LRUs should be informed in the UNLarium inside a single Lexical Realisation Set (LRS).

There are cases, however, in which the definition cannot be lexically realised in the target language. This happens in two situations:

  • When the concept is underspecified, i.e., too broad (or vague) to be realised. The concept of “red entity”, for instance, may be coextensive with several different English LRUs (“blood”, “cherry”, “ruby”, “ketchup”, “Spiderman”, etc), but these are rather subordinate terms (or hyponyms), in the sense they only include and partly match the intended sense. As the expression “red entity” itself is too compositional and too occasional to be considered already lexicalized (Google brings only 8,040 occurrences for this bigram), there will no LRU in this case.
  • When the concept is overspecified, i.e., too narrow (or specific) to be realised. Consider, for instance, the definition “a person who is ready to forgive any transgression a first time and then to tolerate it for a second time, but never for a third time”. This definition does not lead to any LRU in English, French or Russian, even though it corresponds to a single word (“ilunga”) in Tshiluba, a language spoken in the Republic of Congo. We may obviously express the concept in any language, but we have to do it through a periphrasis (as we have done for English) or through a superordinate term (or hypernym), such as “forgiver”, “excuser”, “pardoner”, which are again fairly accurate.

In both cases, there will be no realisation to be informed, and it is important to indicate, in the UNLarium, that the concept has not been lexicalized yet, which means that it can be expressed in the target language only by means of definitions (periphrases) and other semantically related (and inaccurate) LRUs (such as hyponyms or hypernyms). This is done by informing that the Lexical Realisation Set is empty.

Examples

Concept Lexical Realisations Lexical Realisation Unit (LRU)
large gregarious predatory feline of Africa and India having a tawny coat with a shaggy mane in the male lion, lions, king of beasts, kings of beasts, Panthera leo lion, king of beasts, Panthera leo
a female lion lioness, lionesses lioness
a large and densely populated urban area city, cities, metropolis, urban center, urban centers city, metropolis, urban center
the part of the leg of a human being below the ankle joint foot, feet, human foot, human feet, pes foot, human foot, pes
the largest city in New York State and in the United States New York, New York City, NY, NYC New York, New York City, NY, NYC
the corporate executive responsible for the operations of the firm chief executive officer, chief executive officers, chief operating officer, chief operating officers, CEO, CEOs chief executive officer, chief operating officer, CEO
optical instrument consisting of a pair of lenses for correcting defective vision spectacles, specs, eyeglasses, glasses spectacles, specs, eyeglasses, glasses
pale yellowish wine made from white grapes or red grapes with skins removed before fermentation white wine, white wines white wine
a person whose occupation is teaching profesor (male singular), profesores (male plural), profesora (female singular), profesoras (female plural) (Spanish) profesor
solid-hoofed herbivorous quadruped domesticated since prehistoric times cheval (male singular), chevaux (male plural), jument (female singular), juments (female plural) (French) cheval, jument
delighting the senses or exciting intellectual or emotional admiration beautiful beautiful
delighting the senses or exciting intellectual or emotional admiration beau (masculine singular), beaux (masculine plural), belle (feminine singular), belles (feminine plural) (French) beau
have the quality of being to be, be, am, is, are, was, were, being, been be
have a great affection or liking for aime, aimes, aimons, aimez, aiment, aimerais, ai aimé, aimais, ... (French) aimer
steer a vehicle to the side of the road to pull over, pull over, pulls over, pulled over, ... pull over
allow or plan for a certain possibility to take into account, take into account, takes into account, taking into account, ... take into account
on the day preceding today yesterday yesterday
in a willing manner gladly, lief, fain gladly, lief, fain
Software